Submit or Track your Manuscript LOG-IN

Korean Nunchi and Well-Being

SRC_6_1_103-109

 

 

 

Article

Korean Nunchi and Well-Being

Seth Robertson

PhD Candidate in Philosophy, University of Oklahoma

Abstract | “Nunchi” is a Korean term that indicates an expert facility in social interactions and especially the ability to interpret and utilize indirect communication with ease and alacrity. In this paper, I introduce and discuss the concept of nunchi with a focus on two main senses in which it is used: as a skill and as a burden. Then, I discuss the relation of nunchi to well-being and flourishing, both in specifically Korean cultural contexts and in social contexts more generally. Finally, I argue that because of nunchi’s close relation to well-being and flourishing, that there is a strong case to be made for treating it as a virtue.


Editor | Gregg D. Caruso, Corning Community College, SUNY (USA)/Owen Flanagan, Duke University, USA.

Correspondence | Seth Robertson, PhD Candidate in Philosophy, University of Oklahoma; Email: [email protected]

Citation | Robertson, S. (2019). Korean Nunchi and well-being. Science, Religion and Culture, 6(1): 103-109.

DOI | https://dx.doi.org/10.17582/journal.src/2019.6.1.103.109



Introduction

Nunchi (눈치, pronounced noon-tchee), a Korean word meaning literally “eye-measure,” is not widely considered a virtue, even in Korean contexts, but perhaps it should be. Nunchi is the ability both to accurately read others’ mental states by the subtlest of cues and to use this information to expertly steer social situations. The person who deftly directs conversation around sensitive topics has lots of nunchi, the person who constantly puts her foot in her mouth lacks it. In this paper, I introduce and discuss nunchi. I describe two broad senses of nunchinunchi as a skill and nunchi as a burden, and explain how each relates to well-being in both global and in specifically Korean contexts. Finally, I argue that nunchi, at least in the skilled sense, should be treated as a virtue.

 

Skilled Nunchi

Nunchi is a very familiar concept in everyday Korean life and language and has been the focus of quite a bit of Korean scholarship in psychology, communication, and business, but it is probably not widely considered to be deeply philosophically interesting. “Nunchi” has a broad semantic range, and I cannot provide a complete analysis of the term and its usage here. Instead, I will highlight some of the ways in which the term is used that are relevant for this paper. Robinson (1996) provides a review of some English-language descriptions of nunchi: “tact, savoir faire, sense, social sense, perceptiveness, an eye for social situations … to read one’s mind, probe one’s motives, [study] one’s face, [grasp] a situation, [see] how the wind blows” (Martin, Lee, and Chang 1967), or a skill to determine “quickly and accurately…another’s emotions, attitudes, and reaction or likely reaction to a given proposal or situations” (Kalton 1979). Choi and Choi (1992) describe two key features of nunchi: first, that nunchi is especially oriented towards “covert, implicit, or indirect communicative exchanges, and second that nunchi interactions include both “figuring-out” indirect communication and successfully “executing” acts of indirect communication (Choi and Choi 1992, 51). So, in the first major sense of nunchi that we’ll be examining, nunchi means something like an expert, automatic skill in perceiving and deftly reacting to dynamic social and group situations, especially in ways that adroitly track (either intentional or unintentional) indirect communication. Let’s call this sense of the term “skilled nunchi.” Skilled nunchi comes in several levels. A person might “lack” nunchi: they frequently miss fairly obvious social cues or might frequently be rude without realizing it. Importantly, a person who is purposefully rude does not necessarily lack nunchi: unfortunately, some of the worst bullies might have a great deal of nunchi. Less worryingly (and much more commonly) a person might have “slow” nunchi: they are not completely socially oblivious or frequently unintentionally rude to others, but they might occasionally fail to pick up on what in retrospect to them seem to be fairly clear social cues. A person who has “quick” nunchi, however, immediately picks up on even very subtle social cues and navigates them with ease. Interestingly, in Korean contexts, a person can be criticized for having “too much nunchi,” which indicates that either the person is overly strategic or sycophantic in social interactions, or alternatively that a person is overly deferential or submissive.

For our purposes, when I use the term “skilled nunchi” I will be referring to what we might consider “quick nunchi” or nunchi in the most positive sense, unless otherwise noted. In typical Korean usage, while these various attributions of nunchi can be used to indicate more general dispositions, they can also be used in discussing particular acts. For example, I might in general have nunchi, but in some specific instance commit a big social gaffe, and on that occasion, I lacked nunchi. In this way, nunchi corresponds nicely in structure to Whole Trait Theory, a view in contemporary personality psychology (see Fleeson 2001; Fleeson and Jayawickreme 2015; Jayawickreme and Fleeson 2017). Whole trait theory posits personality traits and personality states, which have “the same content as a corresponding trait but…for a shorter duration” (Jayawickreme and Fleeson 2017, 80). Fleeson and Jayawickreme (2017) give a helpful example: “I could have the [personality] state of extraversion for the few minutes I ride the new roller coaster at the amusement park and return to my more common [personality trait of] introversion after the ride” (81).

Some examples of skilled nunchi and the lack thereof might be helpful. Imagine two friends, Ann and Chul-soo, meeting each other for the first time in several months. When they last spoke, Ann told Chul-soo that she been expecting her romantic partner to propose marriage within the next few days. Thirty minutes into the conversation, Chul-soo suddenly asks Ann, without any avarice or ill-intent, whether she has is engaged yet. Chul-soo, in this situation displayed a lack of skilled nunchi. He should have known that Ann had some reason for not bringing up the previously expected engagement, and of the possible reasons why she chose not to, many would be embarrassing or even distressing to share. Alternatively, imagine two graduate students, Sera and Sam, who have recently started dating each other but wish to keep their relationship a secret from their colleagues. Sera, who is in the relationship, is talking to her friend and colleague Ahmed, and accidently lets slip information that implies she is dating Sam. But, Ahmed responds as if he simply did not pick up on the implication, though in fact he did (and if he has highly skilled nunchi, he likely knew of Sera’s relationship already). If Sera also has skilled nunchi, she realizes that Ahmed picked up on the salacious information, and in choosing not to address it, indirectly communicates to her that her secret is safe with him.

It will be useful here to distinguish between skilled nunchi and several similar and related, but ultimately distinct phenomena. First, one might be tempted to equate skilled nunchi with emotional intelligence, which has been defined as “the ability to perceive and express emotion, assimilate emotion in thought, understand and reason with emotion, and regulate emotion in the self and others” (Mayer, Salovey, and Caruso 2000, 396; see also Mayer and Salovey 1997; Mayer et al. 2011). Skilled nunchi allows us to detect a wider range of mental states than only emotions, so it differs from emotional intelligence. Further, a person with skilled nunchi might not be particularly skilled at understanding and reasoning with her own emotions. Second, though skilled nunchi does not pertain only to indirect communication, its strong connotations of skill in indirect communication distinguishes it from the more general notion of social intelligence. This difference is subtle, in part because a person with lots of nunchi will almost always have lots of social intelligence, and vice versa. Third, since skilled nunchi includes expert perceptive capacities, and because a person with skilled nunchi can (intentionally) act impolitely should the situation require, skilled nunchi is not the same as tact, politeness, or civility – though again, they will often go hand-in-hand. Fourth, skilled nunchi is distinct from charisma, though they too often coincide. Some people can be charismatic despite lacking skilled nunchi – think here of an energetic, hilarious, but completely tactless comedian. And some people can have lots of nunchi without being particularly charismatic – especially if they are shy or introverted. Fifth, skilled nunchi is different from mind-reading, the skill helpfully glossed by Hagop Sarkissian as “what we engage in everyday – inferring motives, meanings, and intentions from words, gestures, and expressions” (2010, 9). Skilled nunchi includes this mind-reading ability but is distinct from mind-reading in that nunchi relates not only to our perceptive abilities but also to our reactive behavior, and further it connotes a much greater emphasis on tracking indirect communication than the more generalized notion of mind-reading does. Finally, skilled nunchi is culturally distinct from all of these other notions insofar as it, in addition to tracking mental states like beliefs, emotions, and desires, also tracks group dynamics and shared feelings as well as kibun (기분), pronounced key-boon). Kibun is another important Korean concept, which refers to a mental state relating to mood, atmosphere, climate, dignity, and face. In Korean contexts (especially in professional contexts), there is typically a strong emphasis on maintaining kibun and avoiding social friction and conflict. Doing so well often requires nunchi, and any account of nunchi that does not refer to kibun is incomplete.

Philosophers with backgrounds in Western virtue ethics might be tempted to think that skilled nunchi is identical to or some form of phronesis, or practical wisdom, which Aristotle defined as “a reasoned and true state of capacity to act with regard to human goods” (Nichomachean Ethics IV.5). A person with practical wisdom can perform morally excellent acts across a wide variety of particular situations in which one must weigh competing moral and prudential concerns. But, this equation is incorrect. Skilled nunchi is, in fact, a much narrower concept than practical wisdom. A person with skilled nunchi might (and, in nearly all cases, does) lack (virtuous) practical wisdom, but a person with (virtuous) practical wisdom almost certainly has skilled nunchi. Skilled nunchi allows one to be excellent at certain types of complex and dynamic social interactions, especially those that involve indirect communication and especially ones where tracking kibun is vital. But a person might have skilled nunchi and fail to be generous, or courageous, or humble, or kind. In fact, people with skilled nunchi can be morally vicious – they may use their skilled nunchi to manipulate others for their own selfish ends.

Philosophers with backgrounds in Confucian ethics might wonder how skilled nunchi differs from quan , “moral discretion” or “weighing.” In the Confucian classic Mengzi, a character tries to trip up the eponymous Confucian philosopher Mengzi by posing what is meant to be an attack on the early Confucian emphasis on adherence to ritual. He asks Mengzi whether one should save a drowning sister-in-law even though doing so would break a traditional ritual rule that forbade direct physical contact between certain members of opposite genders (4A17). Mengzi replies, unsurprisingly, that “only a beast would not pull out his sister-in-law if she were drowning,” and that this is a matter of quan (Mengzi 4A17). Saving a drowning person might require quan but it simply does not require skilled nunchi.

 

Burdened Nunchi

There is, however, another broad sense in which the term “nunchi” is used, and this sense is much less positive than that of skilled nunchi. Especially, nunchi in this other sense is often thought to place much greater burden on those with less power or status in social hierarchies (a graduate student must mind or “watch” her nunchi much more carefully than her senior professors need to) and, relatedly, nunchi in this sense is thought of in traditional Korean contexts of putting much more pressure on women than men, and on younger people than older people. In this negative sense, nunchi can mean something like skill in navigating extreme (and typically downward) social pressure. For example, in traditional Korean contexts, the maknae (막내 – pronounced “mang-nae”), or the youngest person (and often, though not at all necessarily the youngest woman) in a group, might have special social expectations to navigate – for example, ensuring that coffee and tea is procured before an office meeting. I will call this more negative sense of the term “burdened nunchi.”

Burdened nunchi shares many features with skilled nunchi. It requires skill in indirect communication, both in interpreting the mental states that others intentionally and unintentionally communicate, and in directly and indirectly communicating with others. However, the purpose of burdened nunchi is often to smooth interactions with colleagues and superiors – even in situations when one would much rather not. One must constantly act in ways that will not upset social harmony or the kibun, even when others (usually superiors) are treating one disrespectfully. Thus, burdened nunchi can be both exhausting and frustrating – one Korean school teacher told me that she wished she could escape from the nunchi of her job, and in that case, she was thinking of nunchi in the sense of burdened nunchi. Burdened nunchi, insofar as it restricts and constrains one’s ability to speak or act as they would like to can quite often be closely related to a sense of dabdabhae (답답해) – a feeling of being so frustrated or stifled by external circumstances in which one cannot act or speak as they want to that it feels as if one is physically suffocating.

Now, it must be pointed out that the distinction I’ve drawn here between skilled nunchi and burdened nunchi is artificial. Like most words with rich and complex meanings, native speakers tend not to carefully distinguish between the different senses of the term, and switch between them often and with ease. However artificial the distinction I’ve drawn here is, I do think it helps us understand some of the complexity of the term “nunchi,” and it will be valuable for thinking about how nunchi is related to well-being and virtue.

 

Nunchi and Flourishing

One major tradition in virtue ethics treats virtues as character traits or dispositions that are especially conducive or even necessary for human flourishing. Do skilled nunchi and burdened nunchi contribute to human flourishing or well-being? In this section, I argue that they do.

The case for skilled nunchi is more straightforward. Skilled nunchi can contribute to well-being or flourishing across a wide a variety of cultural contexts. Most directly, skilled nunchi, like social intelligence more generally benefits us in social situations. Consider the following three cases, in which Nathan possesses skilled nunchi and Lucy lacks it:

Case 1: Nathan and Lucy are professors. When Nathan’s students begin to lose track of the lesson, Nathan immediately recognizes it. He sees their eyes glaze or squint, or start wandering around the room, their posture become more restricted, and generally notices their discomfort or their attention wandering. He is able to stop his lesson and re-engage the students. Lucy, on the other hand, is oblivious that her students are beginning to feel confused, and keeps the lesson moving forward, which only serves to further confuse her students when they do try to pay attention.

Case 2: Nathan and Lucy are at a get-together with several friends. At one point, someone asks Minha, a mutual acquaintance who has recently married, the rather tactless question of how soon she will be having a baby. Lucy thinks this is a fair question – she knows that Minha wanted to have children, so she waits expectantly for an answer. Nathan, however, notices the slightest of frowns in Minha’s face, which she quickly hides. Using his skilled nunchi, Nathan infers that Minha’s discomfort extends past the typical negative reaction to an impolitely private question, and instantly decides that it is especially appropriate to change the subject to spare Minha.

Case 3: Lucy and Nathan are fourth grade co-teachers. Thirty minutes after a group craft math activity finishes, the children begin a new social studies lesson. One of the students, Tucker, who is usually well-behaved, starts to act out. Lucy notices and begins to chastise Tucker. Nathan, however, intervenes and takes Tucker aside. He noticed that Tucker had not been not happy with his assigned groupmates in the craft activity (he wished to be put in a group with his friends), and infers that this is the reason Tucker is acting out. Nathan tells Tucker this. Tucker didn’t realize it himself, but instantly realizes this was the cause of his acting out.

In the Korean context, skilled nunchi is especially important because of the ubiquity of indirect communication. In Korean culture, many types of direct communication can be interpreted as overly confrontational or disruptive of kibun. For example, if I wanted to go out to lunch with a colleague, instead of asking directly whether he wanted to go to lunch, I might instead ask whether he had eaten yet or whether he felt hungry. My colleague should then use skilled nunchi to infer that I am looking for a lunch partner. Similarly, if a teacher has just explained a new theory in her class, and asks her students whether they understand, they might all say “yes” enthusiastically because saying “no” might reflect poorly on the teacher’s explanation and thus disrupt kibun.

So, stepping back, skilled nunchi contributes to well-being or flourishing by helping us navigate social situations in which well-being (and thus flourishing) are at stake. But, what about burdened nunchi? As we’ve seen, burdened nunchi feels exhausting, constricting, and frustrating. Thus, it seems to be straightforwardly bad for well-being or flourishing. But, this inference is too hasty. Lisa Tessman (2005) has argued that there is a distinct and historically unappreciated set of “burdened” virtues “that, while practically necessitated for surviving oppression or morally necessitated for opposing it, carry with them a cost to the bearer” (4). These are virtues that “have the unusual feature of being disjoined from their bearer’s own flourishing” (Tessman 2005, 4). Burdened nunchi is, I think, a type of or closely related to a burdened virtue. And so, while it might be logically closed off from contributing to flourishing, in certain contexts burdened nunchi might be necessary for well-being.

In the Korean context, obedience and deference to authority are traditionally emphasized virtues. Now, we must be careful here. This “culture of obedience” claim can be and has been easily exaggerated, and even problematically and erroneously weaponized in the form of “culture blaming” - for instance in cases of the tragic Sewol ferry disaster in 2014 and in several airline crashes (Ma 2014). Blaming nebulous aspects of a culture for highly specific, complex, multifaceted incidents is a morally fraught practice. The claim I am making here is different, and much more general – that deference towards authority is a historically important value in Korean culture and that this history still affects people today. It remains a common theme in Korean film, television, and literature, and permeates how Koreans might often view their own culture.

Consider the following case. A vice-principal at a middle school grows concerned that students are eating junk food and instead of throwing away the packaging, they litter by just throwing the empty junk food bags to the floor. Thus, he institutes a new rule that teachers must inspect students’ backpacks every morning and confiscate all junk food. The teachers are not enamored with this new policy. Most obviously, it means extra work for them. Further, they are not convinced that the problem is as dire as the vice-principal seems to believe, and it seems that if littering is the issue, it would be more straightforward to just require students to be more proactive in picking up the trash. The teachers might also feel that it is morally inappropriate to have to root through their students’ backpacks. Yet, for many of these teachers, especially those who are young, voicing their discontent at the policy directly to the vice-principal is a non-starter. Doing so could be seen as disruptive. Even those who do feel comfortable criticizing the policy to the vice-principal quickly give up: the vice-principal is quite stubborn. In this situation, the teachers might use their burdened nunchi to express their discontent. They might use their body language, tone of voice, or facial expressions to show to their own students that they would prefer not to search their backpacks, or they might tell the vice-principal “your new policy must have worked: there is much less litter now. Due to the policy’s success, we probably do not need to enforce it as strictly anymore.”

Burdened nunchi has the general structure of a burdened virtue. A person with greater social status would be able to more directly confront some issue head-on, instead of needing to carefully tip-toe around it using her burdened nunchi. Burdened nunchi becomes a survival skill for those without power or social status. There is little doubt that those whose social positions necessitate the use of burdened nunchi would be better off if they did not need to utilize it. Further, burdened nunchi can interfere with the development of non-burdened virtues. For example, it will be difficult to develop or acquire moral courage, and specifically the moral courage to confront those with greater social power or social status, if one is never put into situations in which acts of moral courage can succeed (e.g., if attempted acts of moral courage are viewed as simple disobedience and harshly punished without any positive outcome).

 

Skilled Nunchi and Virtue

Skilled nunchi can contribute to well-being or flourishing in a meaningful way, but is it a virtue? This is not an easy question to answer. The most directly relevant philosophical work here is likely Nancy Snow’s (2009) Virtue as Social Intelligence. Therein, Snow explores a set of interesting claims concerning the relation of virtue and social intelligence: that some virtues are best characterized as forms of social intelligence, that some virtues require social intelligence to produce good results, and that having social intelligence will contribute to the virtuous person being able to use virtues not only to help others but to do so in ways that contribute to her own well-being (Snow 2009). Of these three claims, only the first does not also apply to skilled nunchi – I can think of no other virtue that should be characterized as a form of skilled nunchi. However, it is clear that skilled nunchi can contribute to the success of virtuous acts in much the same was as social intelligence does: in giving us access to the mental states of others, it helps us to better commit kind or generous or caring acts, for example. Similarly, having skilled nunchi will help us to achieve our own life goals and to manage our own well-being in ways that least interfere with acting virtuously towards others.

There are, however, reasons to think that skilled nunchi might not be a virtue. One might argue that, given its sometimes negative connotations, and given that it is closely related to a burdened virtue, that we should not treat it as a virtue. But, it is not clear that this argument succeeds. After all, many virtue terms have senses and usages in which they do not indicate positive moral value. For example, one can be criticized for being “too kind,” “too generous,” or “too humble,” even though kindness, generosity, and humility are virtues. But we can abstract away from these problematic associations to identify virtues of genuine moral value. Thus, the mere fact that some senses of the term “nunchi” fail to connote positive moral value does not mean that there is no sense of the term that represents a virtue. There is another argument nearby that is worth addressing here. One might claim that skilled nunchi is not a virtue because it is morally neutral – whether it produces good results or contributes to well-being or flourishing depends entirely on the presence of other virtues, such as kindness, compassion, and honesty. There is something to this argument, and I must admit that I find it partially plausible. Yet, at least in this form, it might be too demanding. After all, most virtues, if they could be held by a person who had no other virtues, would not reliably produce impressive moral results. A person who is honest but lacks kindness and tact is cruel, a person who is generous but lacks self-control, discretion, and street-smarts will give away money to unworthy causes, a person who is courageous but not morally wise will make bad moral decisions, courageously. Virtues support each other – and it seems that skilled nunchi supports other virtues and that other virtues support it.

Another concern might go something like this. Nunchi is deeply tied to acting with politeness, manners, etiquette, and civility. But, there are important ethical challenges related to all of these (Stohr 2012; Calhoun 2000; Olberding 2015, 2016). Not only do some situations morally require that we behave uncivilly, emphasizing civility as a virtue might encourage people to behave civilly even when they are morally obligated not to. For example, we might find ourselves choosing not criticize a person for a slightly offensive but clearly problematic comment made in casual conversation because doing so would feel impolite. One might claim that treating nunchi as a virtue exacerbates this problem, because behaving with nunchi might overvalue maintaining smooth social atmospheres or kibun compared to other important moral considerations. That is, concern for skilled nunchi might encourage us to overvalue concern for social harmony, atmosphere, mood, and face. I think this is, in general, a very important worry. But, while acknowledging that there are certainly situations in which morality demands that we behave uncivilly, we should first be careful not overestimate the numbers and types of these situations. There are many situations in which remaining civil while still subtly communicating moral disapprobation may be a better option that dropping all pretenses of civility. But, more importantly, when one realizes that she is morally obligated to behave uncivilly or rudely because of other important moral considerations, having skilled nunchi will allow one to do so in the most effective ways.

 

Conclusion

In this essay, I have discussed two broad senses of nunchi. Skilled nunchi is an expert, automatic skill in perceiving and deftly reacting to dynamic social and group situations, especially in ways that adroitly track (either intentional or unintentional) indirect communication. Burdened nunchi is a skill in navigating extreme (and typically downward) social pressure. I discussed the relation between skilled nunchi, burdened nunchi, and well-being or flourishing. Finally, I argued that there some strong reasons for considering skilled nunchi a moral virtue.

 

Acknowledgments

This paper has benefitted from discussions with Amy Olberding, Nancy Snow, Sula You, and Sungwoo Um. Parts of this paper have been improved by helpful comments from Michael Puett and questions from the audience at the Harvard East Asia Society Graduate Conference, as well as from questions from the audience and discussions at the International Society for Chinese Philosophy Conference in Singapore. This publication was made possible through the support of a grant from the John Templeton Foundation to the Institute for the Study of Human Flourishing at The University of Oklahoma. The opinions expressed in this publication are those of the author and do not necessarily reflect the views of the John Templeton Foundation, the Institute for the Study of Human Flourishing, or The University of Oklahoma.

 

References

  • Brennan, Samantha. 2016. The Moral Status of Micro-Inequities - In Favor of Institutional Solutions. In Implicit Bias and Philosophy, edited by Michael Brownstein and Jennifer Saul. Vol. 2. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Calhoun, Cheshire. 2000. The Virtue of Civility. Philosophy and Public Affairs 29 (3): 251–75.
  • Choi, Sang-Chin, and Soo-Hyang Choi. 1992. The Conceptualization of Korean Tact, Noon-Chi. In Innovations in Cross-Cultural Psychology, edited by Saburo Iwawaki, Yoshihisa Kashima, and Kwow Leung, 49–61. Berwyn, PA: Swets & Zeitlinger.
  • Fleeson, William. 2001. Toward a Structure- and Process-Integrated View of Personality: Traits as Density Distributions of States. Journal of Personality and Social Psychology 80 (6): 1011–27.
  • Fleeson, William, and Eranda Jayawickreme. 2015. Whole Trait Theory. Journal of Research in Personality 56: 82–92.
  • Jayawickreme, Eranda, and William Fleeson. 2017. Does Whole Trait Theory Work for the Virtues? In Moral Psychology, Volume 5: Virtue and Character, edited by Walter Sinnott-Armstrong and Christian Miller, 75–104. Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
  • Kalton, Michael. 1979. Korean Ideas and Values. The Philip Jaisohn Memorial Papers 7. Elkins Park.
  • Ma, Kai. 2014. South Korean Ferry Sinking Leads to Culture Blaming and Stereotyping. Time. http://time.com/75742/south-korea-ferry-asian-stereotypes-culture-blaming/.
  • Martin, Samuel E., Yang Ha Lee, and Sung-un Chang. 1967. A Korean-English Dictionary. Yale Linguistic Series. New Haven, CT: Yale University Press.
  • Mayer, John D., and Peter Salovey. 1997. What Is Emotional Intelligence? In Emotional Development and Emotional Intelligence: Implications for Educators, edited by Peter Salovey and David Sluyter, 3–31. New York: Basic Books.
  • Mayer, John D., Peter Salovey, and David Caruso. 2000. Models of Emotional Intelligence. In Handbook of Intelligence, edited by Robert J. Sternberg. New York: Cambridge University Press.
  • Mayer, John D., Peter Salovey, David R. Caruso, and Lillia Cherkasskiy. 2011. Emotional Intelligence. In The Cambridge Handbook of Intelligence, edited by Robert J. Sternberg and Scott Barry Kaufman. Cambridge Handbooks in Psychology. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
  • Olberding, Amy. 2015. From Corpses to Courtesy: Xunzi and the Defense of Etiquette. Journal of Value Inquiry 49: 145–59.
  • ———. 2016. Etiquette: A Confucian Contribution to Moral Philosophy. Ethics 126 (2): 422–46.
  • Robinson, James. 1996. Professional Communication in Korea: Playing Things by Eye. IEEE Transactions on Professional Communication 39 (3): 129–34.
  • Sarkissian, Hagop. 2010. Confucius and the Effortless Life of Virtue. History of Philosophy Quarterly 27 (1): 1–16.
  • Snow, Nancy. 2009. Virtue as Social Intelligence: An Empirically Grounded Theory. Routledge.
  • Stohr, Karen. 2012. On Manners. Routledge.
  • Tessman, Lisa. 2005. Burdened Virtues: Virtue Ethics for Liberatory Struggles. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
  • Van Norden, Bryan W., trans. 2008. Mengzi - With Selections from Traditional Commentaries. Hackett.

 

Endnotes

[1] For example, Samantha Brennan has discussed the potential moral value of “micro-sanctions” (see Brennan 2016).

To share on other social networks, click on any share button. What are these?

Pakistan Journal of Zoology

October

Pakistan J. Zool., Vol. 56, Iss. 5, pp. 2001-2500

Featuring

Click here for more

Subscribe Today

Receive free updates on new articles, opportunities and benefits


Subscribe Unsubscribe